The Limits of "Epistemic Injustice" in the Clinic

Sick people often report frustration about their encounters with doctors: they report not being listened to, not being taken seriously, not being able to successfully communicate their issues, not getting answers to their questions, and more. In 2014, Havi Carel and Ian James Kidd published a paper where they analysed this phenomenon in terms of epistemic injustice. This paper has been enormously influential, to the point where it has become the main lens through which patient frustrations with their doctors is analysed today. In this blog post, I want to highlight some of the limits of this approach.

The notion was introduced by Miranda Fricker in her 2007 book Epistemic Injustice. She defines epistemic injustice as a form of injustice that affects the subject “specifically in their capacity as a knower”. This is somewhat obscure, but the two subtypes of epistemic injustice that she defines help shed some light on the phenomenon she's trying to elucidate. Firstly, she discusses testimonial injustice, which she explains occurs when one's testimony is discounted on account of one's membership of an oppressed group. The idea is that, because of negative stereotypes associated with one's social group, one is believed less than one otherwise would be. For instance, because of stereotypes that paint women as unreliable, irrational, emotional, etc, a woman might be given less credibility when reporting a set of facts than she would have had she been a man. Secondly, Fricker discusses hermeneutic injustice, which occurs when the set of concepts that a given society has unfairly prevents a group of people from making sense of their experiences. She illustrates this phenomenon by pointing to the fact of sexual harassment before groups of feminists coined the term. The idea is that women were subjected to a form of harm that could not be articulated using the socially available concepts. 

Carel and Kidd argue that these notions can help us make sense of the frustration that many people feel in their encounters with doctors. They explain that sick people are viewed through a prejudicial lens as “cognitively unreliable, emotionally compromised, or existentially unstable”. As a result of this prejudice, doctors often fail to ascribe the right amount of credibility to sick people's reports, and their testimony is often “dismissed as irrelevant, confused, too emotional, unhelpful, or time-consuming”. In this way, sick people are subjected to a testimonial injustice: they are afforded less credibility than they should be because of negative stereotypes about them as a group. Moreover, the dominant concepts used in the clinic are, according to Carel and Kidd, not particularly well-suited to making sense of illness. They privilege 'objective' measures of health and disease that are of course important, but cannot capture the lived reality of illness. In this way, the set of concepts available in the clinic do not allow patients to make sense of their experiences, and they are subjected to a hermeneutic injustice

In some illnesses, the frustrations of sick people are particularly pronounced. This is the case especially with what I called "controversialised" diseases in a previous blog post, such as myalgic encephalomyelitis (ME). In a 2017 paper, Charlotte Blease, Havi Carel, and Keith Geraghty attempt to make sense of this intense frustration by appealing to the epistemic injustice framework. They begin with the observation that many people with ME report “feeling dissatisfied, disbelieved, and distressed” in their encounters with doctors. They present ME as a “contested” disease, one over whose aetiology “controversy exists”. They suggest that the disagreement between the biomedical and psychosomatic schools of thought on the disease is of a purely scientific, apolitical nature: the problem, according to them, is that “medical science has yet to explain” its aetiology and pathophysiology. As such, they refuse to take a stance on this dispute, and despite acknowledging the existence of a strained disagreement between doctors and their patients about the validity of the psychosomatic approach to ME, they locate the epistemic injustice that patients face elsewhere. 

They argue in the first instance that patients suffer from testimonial injustice, not in the domain of medical knowledge, but in the domain of phenomenological knowledge: the distinctively first-personal knowledge that patients have about their lived experience of illness. They argue that this knowledge is unfairly discounted by doctors who hold prejudicial beliefs about people with ME. But this restriction to the phenomenological aspects of illness is unstable. Doctors usually concede that the patient has first-personal authority over their own experience: they are careful nowadays not to contradict pure experiential reports (“I believe that you feel that way”). But the experiential reports that doctors do accept are so thinned out that they become entirely subjective. The patient who is viewed through a psychosomatic lens cannot be seen as reliable when they assert that their functional limitations have gotten worse; they can only be seen as reliable in their assertion that they have the impression that it has. The scope of their domain of expertise is shrunk to such an extent that any attempt to assert an objective fact about their disease, such as, for instance, that it has worsened, makes medical presuppositions—here, the presupposition that the patient does have a well-defined disease, which can get worse. In other words, experiential claims are either so thinned out as to not be testimony in any robust sense, or they are thick enough to count as testimony, but they become indissociable from medical claims.

Thus, the contention between doctors and patients cannot be restricted to the experiential domain: it necessarily overspills into the medical domain. But Blease et al, we have seen, refuse to take a stance about which theoretical approach to ME is the right one. As such, they cannot assert that people with ME are subjected to a form of epistemic injustice when their testimony about the physical basis of ME is discounted, whether this is first-personal reports that e.g. their own disease has progressed with exertion, or the presentation of scientific evidence on the pathophysiology of PEM. Instead, they must restrict themselves to the much weaker claim that the problem, in the medical domain, is that patients cannot “voice a different viewpoint” without “feel[ing] belittled or even minimised”. They describe this as an epistemic injustice, but it is unclear how it can be one: the problem they identify is not that doctors fail to ascribe due credibility to their patients’ testimony, but that they do not treat their patients with enough respect when they profess to holding different opinions. To solve this problem, doctors do not need to start believing their patients, they simply need to stop being rude. The harm to which they subject their patient is a failure of politeness, perhaps even respect, but it's not an epistemic injustice. 

Without an independent assessment of the reliability of patients’ and doctors’ knowledge on the medical aspects of ME, it is simply impossible to determine whether the dispute between patients and doctors is an epistemic injustice. This is vividly illustrated by Eleanor Byrne’s response to Blease et al. Byrne presents claims made by doctors to the effect that an ME diagnosis is a “self-fulfilling prophecy”, that it “prevents [patients] from engaging fully with the existential conditions of their lives which is what they can’t cope with”, and that it “set[s] them off on a track which will get them nowhere”, because they’re “just looking for a label”. She explains that these claims need not be seen as indicative of epistemic injustice, for they “demonstrate sensitivity to legitimate and potentially fruitful paths of inquiry”. In other words, doubting and undermining patients’ claims about the pathophysiology of their disease is not an injustice against patients, but simply good science. Byrne goes as far as to argue that to “negatively stereotyp[e]” doctors as prejudiced against their patients is to commit an epistemic injustice against them. 

Whether the clinical encounter involves testimonial injustice therefore depends on substantive views about the plausibility of the two approaches to the aetiology of ME. This is not surprising, since testimonial injustice, by definition, is the ascription of a lower degree of credibility to an agent than the one they ought to be ascribed. The degree of credibility an agent ought to be ascribed therefore needs to be fixed before an assessment can be made whether a particular ascription of credibility constitutes or not an epistemic injustice. To determine whether people with ME suffer a testimonial injustice when their testimony about the objective aspects of their illness is discounted, we therefore need to evaluate the reliability of this testimony. If one believes that people with ME are not reliable when it comes to the objective aspects of their disease, one should conclude, as Byrne appears to, that testimonial injustice does not occur. If on the other hand, one believes, perhaps on the basis of considerations I outlined in a previous blog post, that people with ME are reliable when it comes to the objective aspects of their illness, one can conclude, as I do, that testimonial injustice does occur: people with ME are judged less reliable than they in fact are, by virtue of widely held prejudices against patient competence in general, and against the rationality and integrity of people with ME more specifically. 

***

Once the reliability of people with ME and the corresponding unreliability of their doctors is accepted, the epistemic injustice framework can be used to accurately describe several aspects of the clinical encounter. As we have just seen, it can yield the verdict that doctors who, as a result of their conception of patients as incompetent, unreliable, and untrustworthy, fail to recognise their testimonial authority, thereby commit a testimonial injustice. Are patients also subjected to a hermeneutic injustice, where they are unfairly deprived of the concepts needed to make sense of their experience? I explained in a previous blog post that, while ME was originally understood as characterised by temporary or permanent progression with exertion, that is, by post-exertional malaise (PEM), it was redefined by controversialisers as consisting primarily of feelings of fatigue. This eclipsing of PEM allowed a turn away from biomedical investigation into its pathophysiology, and towards psychologising theories of subjective fatigue states. These theories made their way to practising clinicians, and now constitute the framework through which almost all of them apprehend people with ME. This framework not only leads doctors to form harmful interpretations of their patients as fakers and malingerers, but it also actively hinders the sense-producing activities of people with ME: most saliently, it prevents them from being able to communicate to their doctors that their reason for restricting their activity levels is not that they feel too fatigued, but rather that they are seeking to avoid PEM.

One might be tempted to theorise this in the terms of hermeneutic injustice. Fricker originally defined hermeneutic injustice as a generalised conceptual impoverishment, that is unfairly produced, and that results in the unintelligibly of the experiences of the dominated, to both the dominant and the dominated. This definition does not apply to our case: while the epistemic resources of physicians do prevent them from accurately cognising the phenomenon at hand, this problem is not shared by communities of sick people, for as we have seen, these communities have developed a sophisticated conceptual apparatus with which to make sense of their disease, and much of their advocacy consists in attempting to increase the uptake of this apparatus among those tasked with researching and treating their disease. Thus, we are not dealing with a case of hermeneutic injustice as Fricker originally defined it. However, Fricker’s work has been developed in generative ways by other scholars. For instance, Rebecca Mason, drawing on the work of Charles Mills has proposed widening the notion to include situations in which dominated groups do have adequate conceptual resources, but these are not recognised or respected by dominant groups, such that theirs is a state of “wilfully sustained ignorance”. In such situations, the dominant actively ignore or dismiss the hermeneutic resources produced by the dominated, and continue to use (Kristie Dotson) or even produce new (Han Edgoose) conceptual resources that stabilise and worsen the harm they incur. This illuminatingly describes the hermeneutic aspects of the epistemic injustice which people with ME incur in the clinic. 

The epistemic injustice framework, once supplemented with an evaluation of knowledge claims, can therefore be usefully applied to the case of ME. It can afford us, as Blease et al had contended, an understanding of what goes wrong in the clinic both testimonially and hermeneutically: people with ME are wrongfully disbelieved, and are incapacitated in their attempts to communicate their experience of illness. But Blease et al’s hope that an examination of epistemic injustice in the clinical encounter can exhaustively explain the discontent of people with ME and their conflicts with their doctors risks eliding some of the non-epistemic and arguably more serious harms that doctors inflict on people with ME. For it is one thing not to be believed, not to be understood; and it is quite another to be kept sick, to be made sicker, and to be killed. A narrow focus on epistemic injustice risks emphasising the harms that patients incur as knowers at the expense of the harm they incur as patients. 

I explained in a previous blog post that psychologising theories serve as reasons for denying care: if a particular symptom is the result of anxiety rather than that of a pathological physiological process, pharmacological intervention besides anxiolytic medication is not warranted. I also explained that they serve as reasons to coerce patients into harmful treatment: if the symptoms are the result of reduced activity, incitation into increased activity presents itself as a salient therapeutic option. These twin forms of neglect and harm can cause disease progression, such that incalculably many people have become unable to work, housebound, or bedbound as a result. They can also cause death: people with very severe forms of ME can become unable to ingest sufficient nutrition, usually because they are too weak to chew, swallow, and digest food. They almost always struggle to receive nutritional support from doctors who refuse to acknowledge that they cannot sustain themselves nutritionally, and in some cases, they starve to death as a result. In light of this, I contend that what primarily explains the feelings of dissatisfaction on the part of people with ME is not, as Blease et al suggest, that they are disbelieved and unheard, but that they are actively neglected and harmed. 

An excessively narrow focus on epistemic injustice can obscure this. For instance, in their study of epistemic injustice among people with ME, Joanne Hunt et al interview a woman called Elizabeth, who says of doctors: “they are just trying to kill you off ”. Hunt et al propose the following interpretation of this comment: “Elizabeth appears to experience epistemic injustice as existential erasure”. This remark appears amidst a discussion of what Hunt et al call the “existential harms” that people with ME incur: Igor, one of their interviewees, explains that as a result of his illness not being taken seriously, “[he] just felt like [he] wasn’t treated like a human being”. But later in the paper, Hunt et al cite Elizabeth again as explaining having been coerced into a graded exercise regimen which worsened her illness to the point that she was having seizures. In light of this, I think that we should interpret Elizabeth’s assertion, not figuratively as an expression of existential erasure in reaction to an epistemic injustice, but literally, as an expression of terror at the fact that people who have life-or-death power over her are physically harming her in unbearable and possibly limitless ways. 

It is true that, should doctors cease to treat their patients in epistemically unjust ways, much of this harm would be mitigated. Doctors who believe their patients about the existence and harm of PEM do not only make them feel heard and perhaps even understood, but they are also much less likely to suggest or impose graded exercise problems that cause disease progression. But a horizon where doctors listen to their patients adequately falls significantly short of what sick people need. For they need not only to be heard, but also for their doctors to be actively competent in the management of their disease. This requires much more than an end to epistemic injustice in the clinic: it requires a radical overhaul to the knowledge production and dissemination mechanisms that underlie ME healthcare, so as to ensure that doctors' beliefs about ME are responsive to scientific evidence, as well as, possibly, structural changes in the provision of healthcare more generally. The epistemic injustice that sick people do incur in the clinic is not the main form of harm they incur, and it is not what needs addressing if people with ME are to be treated well, not only in their capacities as knowers, but also in their capacities as patients.

A 4 panel illustrated image. The top-left panel shows a hand reaching up out of a choppy body of water, with the text 'I need competent healthcare'.  The top-right panel shows the same hand along with another hand, out of the water, emerging from the edge of the frame, reaching towards the hand in the water.  The bottom-left panel shows the other hand high-fiving the hand in the water. The arm of the high-fiving hand has a doctor's coat sleeve photoshopped on to it. Beside it is the text 'I hear you. I believe you.  The bottom-right panel shows the hand in the water sinking below the surface. Above it is the text 'Thanks...I Guess?'


Comments

  1. Thank you for this.

    I think epistemic injustice within the clinical encounter, in order to be plausible and coherent as a concept, should, indeed, be viewed in relation to the exclusion and/or devaluation of patients in their capacity as a knower within the wider infrastructure of epistemic processes (i.e. academia, gray literature, decision-making on research programs, development of guidelines).

    Epistemic and non-epistemic harms in the clinical encounter can then be understood as downstream effects of epistemic injustice within other spaces (in which patients may well not be ‘in the room’ or, if they are, may be undervalued/underutilized as knowers within the epistemic enterprise).

    In the case of ME/CFS, patients generally subscribe to a (bio)medical disease model they feel most accurately describes their illness experience, whereas they generally reject and contest a (bio)psychosocial illness (without disease) model they feel does not. How do we conceptually make sense of the relationship between illness experience and illness/disease model?

    Here, psychosomatic medicine seems to want it both ways: there are subjective embodied states and there are objective biological states, the two are intricately linked (the old ‘body and mind are one’ chestnut), but patients only have access to the first and are mistaken in their experience of how it relates to the latter. In effect, they have epistemic privilege about neither illness nor disease states.

    I tend to think patients’ epistemic privilege can comprise a significant overlap between their knowledge about the lived experience in their body as a subject and their knowledge about pathophysiological processes in their body as an object. The most unequivocal example where this could be the case, would be if a patient is also a doctor (but there are various configurations of situated knowledge in which the two may overlap). Either way, patients would generally seem well-placed as arbiters in knowledge production about their illness/disease. (This, of course, is what is primarily contested in ‘contested’ illness/disease.)

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. I completely agree with you that the harms patients incur in the clinic are downstream effects of what happens in other spaces (research labs, public health agencies, journal editorial offices, funding bodies, etc), but I'm not sure I'd understand what happens in those spaces in terms of epistemic injustice. It is a problem, in my opinion, that sick people are not involved or not involved enough in decisions surrounding funding allocations, guideline creation, publications, etc. But I don't think this meets the definition for a testimonial injustice (the problem is not that sick people's testimony is discounted, it is that they do not have control over the processes that are supposedly for them), nor for a hermeneutic injustice (the problem is not that hermeneutic resources in these spaces cannot capture the experience of sick people). So although I do agree with you that the problems in the clinic are really expressions of larger problems about scientific research and healthcare in general, I don't think epistemic injustice is quite the framework to make sense of that either.

      I wouldn't say that the reason sick people reject the psychosomatic model for their disease is that they 'feel it doesn't describe their illness experience', at least if we understand 'illness experience' in the very thin sense of simply one's subjective impressions of what it's like to be sick. The reason they/we reject it is that it is inconsistent with biomedical evidence about the pathophysiology of our disease, and with things we all experience that can be measured: PEM, orthostatic intolerance, allergic reactions, etc. I don't think sick people who are trained as doctors have an advantage when it comes to this actually; quite the opposite! Often doctors are trained to dismiss ME and associated conditions as psychosomatic and this plays a role in delaying their recognition that this is not what is happening to them.

      But I absolutely agree with you that sick people are very well placed to understand what is happening to them, physiologically. This is not primarily because they have first-personal experience of the symptoms of the disease, though that helps to recognise certain errors that scientists and doctors make, such as defining the disease in terms of fatigue rather than PEM, but because they have an immediate and direct incentive to figure out what is going on with them. They have an incentive to know, for instance, that CBT and GET are harmful treatments, and therefore that the psychosomatic view of ME is false. These incentives to detect errors are not everything, but they are important I think in explaining how and where sick people are trustworthy about the medical aspects of their disease!

      Delete
    2. Thank you for your thoughtful response.

      There is a distinctively epistemic quality to contested illness/disease, but I’m amenable to conceding that there is a conceptual shortfall in framing it as epistemic injustice. There is also a paradox to patient representation: the most vocal/visible patients are liable to not be representative of less vocal/visible patients in some way(s). Therefore, I’m alive to the likelihood that non-dominant hermeneutic resources may not be as forthcoming to the wider patient population as they are to those that have acquired them.

      I had a sense that using the word ‘feel’ might be problematic. Of course, the evidence is in patients’ favor, so the psychosomatic model is inappropriate/obsolete regardless of anyone’s feelings. However, the state of the art has been hard-won by patients; the whole problem with the psychosomatic model is that it thrives in the (relative) absence of evidence and becomes invested in maintaining that status quo. Its perceived plausibility, then, is a function of its perceived narrative power/appeal. Historically, the psychosomatic model for ‘illness without disease’ is a reiterated solution looking for a problem.

      I’m trying to conceive of this dynamic epistemologically and phenomenologically, of what initiates and perpetuates it. At one point, psychiatry advanced its contestation of the biomedical model of ME and, at another point, patients advanced their contestation of the biopsychosocial model of CFS. When science is not working for patients, but this is not the scientific consensus, what grounds their situated knowledge about their illness/disease? (Indeed, doctors who are patients may also have a disadvantage here precisely because they are ill-equipped with dominant hermeneutic resources for their contested condition.)

      An obvious answer, which you’ve tabled as well, seems to be the patient community. Information control is implicated in the psychosomatic model, framing free information exchange between patients as a social factor in the promotion of inappropriate illness behavior (i.e. ‘social contagion’, ‘secondary gains’, ‘collusion’). But there are barriers to peer support, such as diagnostic delay or even outright diagnosis withholding due to the perceived threat of medicalization; falling ill and becoming part of the patient community do not typically coincide chronologically and some patients may remain isolated indefinitely (in which case they are likely deprived of hermeneutic resources to articulate their illness/disease). My sense is that the patient community is the tip of the iceberg.

      Delete
    3. Sorry for the delay in replying--I didn't see your reply and don't get notifications... sorry!

      I completely agree with you that there is a small minority of sick people (myself included!) who claim to speak for the interests of everyone who also has ME; except that most people who have ME don't know that they do, and some people who do knowingly have ME also align themselves with the biopsychosocial model. So it's not straightforward, because our mandate to speak on behalf of people with ME in general is not very well grounded in the kind of procedures one could think of, like for instance voting. My take on this is that this is a very common feature of political movements, where a smaller number of people are more actively involved, and distill the experiences of the group into a critical standpoint that they claim represents the interests of the population as a whole, including those who are not in the community in any way. This gives rise to all sorts of questions---and potential problems! But it doesn't seem to me that this problem is specific to the case of ME or other controversialised diseases---I think it applies in many social movements. And we shouldn't diminish the very real fact that the vast majority of people who do have ME agree with and contribute to the development of this standpoint.

      But I'm also not sure I would say that it's because communities of sick people prefer a biomedical approach that it should be taken on. It's because it's true that it should be taken on! Sick people have better truth-detection mechanisms than non-sick researchers because we have a direct incentive in the truth about our disease (because a true theory is much more likely to yield an effective treatment). So I'd say that our shared opinion is a good *signal* for the truth---better than the shared opinions of scientists who are paid by the state to find ways to refuse us benefit payments---but it's not the grounds for which the biomedical approach should be adopted. As you say, there is a distinctly epistemic dimension to this debate!

      Delete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

Capital and the Controversialisation of Illness

Welcome!

Debates on the Nature of Disease